In evolutionary biology, the Baldwin effect describes an effect of learned behaviour on evolution. James Mark Baldwin and others suggested that an organism's ability to learn new behaviours (e.g. to acclimatise to a new stressor) will affect its reproductive success and will therefore have an effect on the genetic makeup of its species through natural selection. It posits that subsequent selection might reinforce the originally learned behaviors, if adaptive, into more in-born, instinctive ones. Though this process appears similar to Lamarckism, that view proposes that living things inherited their parents' acquired characteristics. The Baldwin effect only posits that learning ability, which is genetically based, is another variable in / contributor to environmental adaptation. First proposed during the Eclipse of Darwinism in the late 19th century, this effect has been independently proposed several times, and today it is generally recognized as part of the modern synthesis.

The Baldwin effect compared to Lamarck's theory of evolution, Darwinian evolution, and Waddington's genetic assimilation. All the theories offer explanations of how organisms respond to a changed environment with adaptive inherited change.

"A New Factor in Evolution"

edit

The effect, then unnamed, was put forward in 1896 in a paper "A New Factor in Evolution" by the American psychologist James Mark Baldwin, with a second paper in 1897.[1][2] The paper proposed a mechanism for specific selection for general learning ability. As the historian of science Robert Richards explains:[3]

If animals entered a new environment—or their old environment rapidly changed—those that could flexibly respond by learning new behaviours or by ontogenetically adapting would be naturally preserved. This saved remnant would, over several generations, have the opportunity to exhibit spontaneously congenital variations similar to their acquired traits and have these variations naturally selected. It would look as though the acquired traits had sunk into the hereditary substance in a Lamarckian fashion, but the process would really be neo-Darwinian.[3]

Selected offspring would tend to have an increased capacity for learning new skills rather than being confined to genetically coded, relatively fixed abilities. In effect, it places emphasis on the fact that the sustained behaviour of a species or group can shape the evolution of that species. The "Baldwin effect" is better understood in evolutionary developmental biology literature as a scenario in which a character or trait change occurring in an organism as a result of its interaction with its environment becomes gradually assimilated into its developmental genetic or epigenetic repertoire.[4][5] In the words of the philosopher of science Daniel Dennett:[6]

Thanks to the Baldwin effect, species can be said to pretest the efficacy of particular different designs by phenotypic (individual) exploration of the space of nearby possibilities. If a particularly winning setting is thereby discovered, this discovery will create a new selection pressure: organisms that are closer in the adaptive landscape to that discovery will have a clear advantage over those more distant.[6]

An update to the Baldwin effect was developed by Jean Piaget, Paul Weiss, and Conrad Waddington in the 1960s–1970s. This new version included an explicit role for the social in shaping subsequent natural change in humans (both evolutionary and developmental), with reference to alterations of selection pressures.[7]

Subsequent research shows that Baldwin was not the first to identify the process; Douglas Spalding mentioned it in 1873.[8]

Controversy and acceptance

edit

Initially Baldwin's ideas were not incompatible with the prevailing, but uncertain, ideas about the mechanism of transmission of hereditary information and at least two other biologists put forward very similar ideas in 1896.[9][10] In 1901, Maurice Maeterlinck referred to behavioural adaptations to prevailing climates in different species of bees as "what had merely been an idea, therefore, and opposed to instinct, has thus by slow degrees become an instinctive habit".[11] The Baldwin effect theory subsequently became more controversial, with scholars divided between "Baldwin boosters" and "Baldwin skeptics".[12] The theory was first called the "Baldwin effect" by George Gaylord Simpson in 1953.[12] Simpson "admitted that the idea was theoretically consistent, that is, not inconsistent with the modern synthesis",[12] but he doubted that the phenomenon occurred very often, or if so, could be proven to occur. In his discussion of the reception of the Baldwin-effect theory Simpson points out that the theory appears to provide a reconciliation between a neo-Darwinian and a neo-Lamarckian approach and that "Mendelism and later genetic theory so conclusively ruled out the extreme neo-Lamarckian position that reconciliation came to seem unnecessary".[4] In 1942, the evolutionary biologist Julian Huxley promoted the Baldwin effect as part of the modern synthesis, saying the concept had been unduly neglected by evolutionists.[4][13][14]

In the 1960s, the evolutionary biologist Ernst Mayr contended that the Baldwin effect theory was untenable because

  1. the argument is stated in terms of the individual genotype, whereas what is really exposed to the selection pressure is a phenotypically and genetically variable population;
  2. it is not sufficiently emphasized that the degree of modification of the phenotype is in itself genetically controlled;
  3. it is assumed that phenotypic rigidity is selectively superior to phenotypic flexibility.[15]

In 1987 Geoffrey Hinton and Steven Nowlan demonstrated by computer simulation that learning can accelerate evolution, and they associated this with the Baldwin effect.[16][17][18]

Paul Griffiths[19] suggests two reasons for the continuing interest in the Baldwin effect. The first is the role mind is understood to play in the effect. The second is the connection between development and evolution in the effect. Baldwin's account of how neurophysiological and conscious mental factors may contribute to the effect[20][21][1] brings into focus the question of the possible survival value of consciousness.[22]

 
The house finch's colonisation of North America has provided empirical evidence of the Baldwin effect.[23]

Still, David Depew observed in 2003, "it is striking that a rather diverse lot of contemporary evolutionary theorists, most of whom regard themselves as supporters of the Modern Synthesis, have of late become 'Baldwin boosters'".[12] These

are typically evolutionary psychologists who are searching for scenarios in which a population can get itself by behavioral trial and error onto a "hard to find" part of the fitness landscape in which human brain, language, and mind can rapidly coevolve. They are searching for what Daniel Dennett, himself a Baldwin booster, calls an "evolutionary crane," an instrument to do some heavy lifting fast.[12]

According to Dennett, also in 2003, recent work has rendered the Baldwin effect "no longer a controversial wrinkle in orthodox Darwinism".[6] Potential genetic mechanisms underlying the Baldwin effect have been proposed for the evolution of natural (genetically determinant) antibodies.[24] In 2009, empirical evidence for the Baldwin effect was provided from the colonisation of North America by the house finch.[23]

The Baldwin effect has been incorporated into the extended evolutionary synthesis.[25][26][27]

Comparison with genetic assimilation

edit

The Baldwin effect has been confused with, and sometimes conflated with, a different evolutionary theory also based on phenotypic plasticity, C. H. Waddington's genetic assimilation. The Baldwin effect includes genetic accommodation, of which one type is genetic assimilation.[28] Science historian Laurent Loison has written that "the Baldwin effect and genetic assimilation, even if they are quite close, should not be conflated".[29]

See also

edit
  • Evolvability – Capacity of a system for adaptive evolution
  • Maternal effect – Influence of mother's environment and genotype on offspring's phenotype
  • Meme – Cultural idea which spreads through imitation
  • Pangenesis – Darwin's proposed mechanism for heredity
  • Weismann barrier – Distinction between germ cell lineages producing gametes and somatic cells

Notes

edit
  1. ^ a b Baldwin 1896a.
  2. ^ Baldwin 1897.
  3. ^ a b Richards, Robert J. (1987). Darwin and the Emergence of Evolutionary Theories of Mind and Behavior. The University of Chicago Press. p. 399. ISBN 978-0-226-71199-7.
  4. ^ a b c Simpson 1953.
  5. ^ Newman 2002.
  6. ^ a b c Dennett, Daniel (2003), "The Baldwin Effect: a Crane, not a Skyhook" in: Weber, Bruce H.; Depew, David J. (2003). Evolution and Learning: The Baldwin Effect Reconsidered. MIT Press. pp. 69–106. ISBN 978-0-262-23229-6.
  7. ^ Burman, J. T. (2013). "Updating the Baldwin Effect: The biological levels behind Piaget's new theory". New Ideas in Psychology. 31 (3): 363–373. doi:10.1016/j.newideapsych.2012.07.003.
  8. ^ Noble, R.; Noble, D. (2017) Was the Watchmaker Blind? Or Was She One-Eyed? Biology 2017, 6(4), 47; doi:10.3390/biology6040047, quoting Bateson, P. The adaptability driver: Links between behaviour and evolution. Biol. Theory 2006, 1, 342–345. See also Stigler's law.
  9. ^ Morgan, C. L. (1896). "On modification and variation". Science. 4 (99): 733–740. Bibcode:1896Sci.....4..733L. doi:10.1126/science.4.99.733. PMID 17735249.
  10. ^ Osborne, H. F. (1896). "Ontogenic and phylogenic variation". Science. 4 (100): 786–789. Bibcode:1896Sci.....4..786O. doi:10.1126/science.4.100.786. PMID 17734840.
  11. ^ Materlinck, Maurice (1901). The Life of the Bee. Dodd, Mead and Co. pp. Chapter VII section 102.
  12. ^ a b c d e Depew, David J. (2003), "Baldwin Boosters, Baldwin Skeptics" in: Weber, Bruce H.; Depew, David J. (2003). Evolution and Learning: The Baldwin Effect Reconsidered. MIT Press. pp. 3–31. ISBN 978-0-262-23229-6.
  13. ^ Scheiner, Samuel M. (2014). "The Baldwin Effect: Neglected and Misunderstood". The American Naturalist. 184 (4). University of Chicago Press: ii–iii. Bibcode:2014ANat..184D...2S. doi:10.1086/677944. ISSN 0003-0147. PMID 25354416. S2CID 9214778.
  14. ^ Belew, Richard K. (2018). Adaptive Individuals In Evolving Populations: Models And Algorithms. Taylor & Francis. p. 100. ISBN 978-0-429-97145-7.
  15. ^ Mayr, Ernst (1963). Animal Species and Evolution. Harvard University Press. ISBN 978-0-674-03750-2.
  16. ^ Hinton, Geoffrey E.; Nowlan, Steven J. (1987). "How learning can guide evolution". Complex Systems. 1: 495–502.
  17. ^ Maynard Smith, John (1987). "When learning guides evolution". Nature. 329 (6142): 761–762. Bibcode:1987Natur.329..761S. doi:10.1038/329761a0. PMID 3670381. S2CID 5476916.
  18. ^ Puentedura, Ruben R. (2003). "The Baldwin effect in the age of computation". In Weber, Bruce H.; Depew, David J. (eds.). Evolution and Learning: The Baldwin Effect Reconsidered. MIT press. pp. 219–234. ISBN 9780262232296.
  19. ^ Griffiths, Paul E. (2003). "Beyond the Baldwin effect: James Mark Baldwin's 'social heredity', epigenetic inheritance, and niche construction". In Weber, Bruce H.; Depew, David J. (eds.). Evolution and Learning: The Baldwin Effect Reconsidered. MIT Press. pp. 193–215. ISBN 9780262232296.
  20. ^ Baldwin, J. Mark (1896b). "Heredity and instinct". Science. 3 (64): 438–441, 558–561. Bibcode:1896Sci.....3..438B. doi:10.1126/science.3.64.438. PMID 17780356.
  21. ^ Baldwin, J. Mark (1896c). "Consciousness and evolution". Psychological Review. 3 (3): 300–309. doi:10.1037/h0063996. PMID 17835006.
  22. ^ Lindahl, B. I. B. (2001). "Consciousness, behavioural patterns and the direction of biological evolution: implications for the mind–brain problem". In Pylkkänen, Paavo; Vadén, Tere (eds.). Dimensions of Conscious Experience. John Benjamins. pp. 73–99. ISBN 978-90-272-5157-2.
  23. ^ a b Badyaev, Alexander V. (March 2009). "Evolutionary significance of phenotypic accommodation in novel environments: an empirical test of the Baldwin effect". Philosophical Transactions of the Royal Society of London B. 364 (1520): 1125–1141. doi:10.1098/rstb.2008.0285. PMC 2666683. PMID 19324617.
  24. ^ Anderson, Russell (1996). "How the adaptive antibodies facilitate the evolution of natural antibodies". Immunology and Cell Biology. 74 (2): 286–291. doi:10.1038/icb.1996.50. PMID 8799730. S2CID 20023879.
  25. ^ Pigliucci, Massimo. Phenotypic Plasticity. In Massimo Pigliucci, and Gerd B. Müller (eds), Evolution: The Extended Synthesis (Cambridge, MA, 2010; online edn, MIT Press Scholarship Online, 22 Aug. 2013).
  26. ^ Loison, Laurent (2019). "Canalization and genetic assimilation: Reassessing the radicality of the Waddingtonian concept of inheritance of acquired characters". Semin Cell Dev Biol. 88: 4–13. doi:10.1016/j.semcdb.2018.05.009. PMID 29763656.
  27. ^ Aaby, Bendik Hellem (2022). "The Ecological Dimension of Natural Selection". Philosophy of Science. 88 (5): 1199–1209. doi:10.1086/714999.
  28. ^ Crispo, Erika (2007). "The Baldwin effect and genetic assimilation: revisiting two mechanisms of evolutionary change mediated by phenotypic plasticity". Evolution. 61 (11): 2469–2479. doi:10.1111/j.1558-5646.2007.00203.x. PMID 17714500. S2CID 9292273.
  29. ^ Loison, Laurent (2021). "Epigenetic inheritance and evolution: a historian's perspective". Philosophical Transactions of the Royal Society B: Biological Sciences. 376 (1826). doi:10.1098/rstb.2020.0120. PMC 8059632. PMID 33866812.

References

edit
edit
  NODES
Idea 8
idea 8
Note 3