Wikipedia:Reference desk/Mathematics

(Redirected from Wikipedia:RD/Maths)
Latest comment: 11 hours ago by 2A04:4A43:909F:F9FF:FC7B:F1E8:19D6:124C in topic How did the Romans do engineering calculations?
Welcome to the mathematics section
of the Wikipedia reference desk.
Select a section:
Want a faster answer?

Main page: Help searching Wikipedia

   

How can I get my question answered?

  • Select the section of the desk that best fits the general topic of your question (see the navigation column to the right).
  • Post your question to only one section, providing a short header that gives the topic of your question.
  • Type '~~~~' (that is, four tilde characters) at the end – this signs and dates your contribution so we know who wrote what and when.
  • Don't post personal contact information – it will be removed. Any answers will be provided here.
  • Please be as specific as possible, and include all relevant context – the usefulness of answers may depend on the context.
  • Note:
    • We don't answer (and may remove) questions that require medical diagnosis or legal advice.
    • We don't answer requests for opinions, predictions or debate.
    • We don't do your homework for you, though we'll help you past the stuck point.
    • We don't conduct original research or provide a free source of ideas, but we'll help you find information you need.



How do I answer a question?

Main page: Wikipedia:Reference desk/Guidelines

  • The best answers address the question directly, and back up facts with wikilinks and links to sources. Do not edit others' comments and do not give any medical or legal advice.
See also:


December 11

edit

Unique normal ultrafilter

edit

So I'm supposed to know the answer to this, I suppose, but I don't seem to :-)

"Everyone knows" that, in  , Gödel's constructible universe relative to an ultrafilter   on some measurable cardinal  , there is only a single normal ultrafilter, namely   itself. See for example John R. Steel's monograph here, at Theorem 1.7.

So I guess that must mean that the product measure  , meaning you fix some identification between   and   and then say a set has measure 1 if measure 1 many of its vertical sections have measure 1, must not be normal. (Unless it's somehow just equal to   but I don't think it is.)

But is there some direct way to see that? Say, a continuous function   with   such that the set of fixed points of   is not in the ultrafilter no singleton has a preimage under   that's in the ultrafilter? I haven't been able to come up with it. --Trovatore (talk) 06:01, 11 December 2024 (UTC)Reply



December 15

edit

What is the cause of this paradox?

edit

I recently completed a calculus term, in which one of the last units involving how much one aspect of an object was changing in relation to time at a certain point, given the rate of change of another aspect. Many specific questions could be analyzed as a right triangle with one leg (the x) remaining constant and the other leg (the y) growing at a specified rate. When it came time to solve for the value of the dz/dt (the rate of the hypotenuse’s growth with respect to time) at a certain point, it ended up as less than the provided dy/dt. Here’s an illustration:

The x is the distance from me to a tower. This remains constant.

The y is the distance from the tower to a flying bird.

The dy/dt is the speed at which the bird is flying from the tower.

The z is my distance from the bird.

In this illustration, the distance between me and the bird is increasing at a slower rate than the speed at which the bird itself is flying. What is the cause of this paradox? Primal Groudon (talk) 19:43, 15 December 2024 (UTC)Reply

I do not see any paradox here. Ruslik_Zero 20:30, 15 December 2024 (UTC)Reply
If the bird is between you and the tower (0 ≤ y < x), the distance between you and the bird is even decreasing: dz/dt < 0. By the time it flies right overhead (y = x), the distance is momentarily stationary: dz/dt = 0. After that, it increases: dz/dt > 0. This rate of increase will asymptotically approach dy/dt from below as the bird flies off into an infinite distance.  --Lambiam 00:34, 16 December 2024 (UTC)Reply
I think the issue here is that even though the rate of change of z is less than the rate of change of y, z never actually becomes less than y. You can see this graphically, for example, by comparing the graphs of y=x and y=√(x2+1). The second graph is always above the first graph, but the slope of the first graph is x/√(x2+1), which is always less than 1, the slope of the first graph. But this is typical behavior when a graph has an asymptote. As a simpler example, the slope of 1/x is negative, but the value never goes below 0 (at least for x>0). Similarly, the slope of x+1/x is always less than 1, but the value of x+1/x is always greater than x (again, for x>0). The graph of y=√(x2+1) is one branch of a hyperbola having y=x as an asymptote, and this looks very much like the x>0 part of y=x+1/x. In general the difference in rates of change can imply that that two quantities get closer and closer to each other, but this does not mean they ever become equal. This phenomenon is, perhaps, counterintuitive for many people, but the math says it can happen anyway. I don't know if this rises to the level of a paradox, but I can see that it might be concerning for some. --RDBury (talk) 09:39, 16 December 2024 (UTC)Reply
For x > 0, the graph of y=√(x2+1) looks even more like that of y=x+1/(2x). For example, when x = 5, √(x2+1) = 26 ≈ 5.09902 is approximated much more closely by 5.1 than by 5.2.  --Lambiam 18:35, 16 December 2024 (UTC)Reply



December 19

edit

Who is the following unknown?

edit

When asked "WHO IS YOUR X?" (X still being unknown to me but is known to the respondents), here are the answers I get:

A answers: "A"
B answers: "C"
C answers: "C"
D answers: "F"
E answers: "F"
F answers: "F"

To sum up, the special phenomenon here is that, everybody has their own X (usually), and if any respondent points at another respondent as the first respondent's X, then the other respondent must point at themself as their X.

I wonder who the unknown X may be, when I only know that X is a natural example from everyday life. I thought about a couple of examples, but none of them are satisfactory, as follows:

X is the leader of one's political party, or X is one's mayor, and the like, but all of these examples attribute some kind of leadership or superiority to X, whereas I'm not interested in this kind of solution - involving any superiority of X.

Here is a second solution I thought about: X is the first (or last) person born in the year/month the respondent was born, and the like. But this solution involves some kind of order (in which there is a "first person" and a "last person"), whereas I'm not interested in this kind of solution - involving any order.

Btw, I've published this question also at the Miscellaneous desk, because this question is about everyday life, but now I decide to publish this question also here, because it's indirectly related to a well known topic in Math. 79.177.151.182 (talk) 13:27, 19 December 2024 (UTC)Reply

Head of household comes to mind as a fairly natural one. The colours then correspond to different households which can be just one person. One objection is that "head of household" is a fairy traditional concept. With marriage equality now being the norm it's perhaps outdated. --2A04:4A43:909F:F9FF:397E:BBF9:E80B:CB36 (talk) 15:11, 19 December 2024 (UTC)Reply
I have already referred to this kind of solution, in the example of "my mayor", see above why this solution is not satisfactory. 79.177.151.182 (talk) 15:31, 19 December 2024 (UTC)Reply

The question has been resolved at the Miscellaneous reference desk.

  Resolved

79.177.151.182 (talk) 15:48, 19 December 2024 (UTC)Reply

X may well be 'the oldest living person of your ancestry'. --CiaPan (talk) 20:46, 19 December 2024 (UTC)Reply

Resolved or not, let's try to analyze this mathematically. Given is some set   and some function   For the example,   with      
Knowing that "everybody has their own X (usually)", we can normalize the unusual situation that function   might not be total in two ways. The first is to restrict the set   to the domain of   that is, the set of elements on which   is defined. This is possible because of the condition that   implies   so this does not introduce an undue limitation of the range of   The second approach is to postulate that   whenever   might otherwise be undefined. Which of these two approaches is chosen makes no essential difference.
Let   be the range of  , given by:
 
Clearly, if   we have   We know, conversely, that   implies  
Let us also consider the inverse image of  , given by:
 
Suppose that   This means that there exists some   which in turns means that   But then we know that   Combining this, we have,
 
The inverse-image function restricted to   to which we assign the typing
 
now induces a partitioning of   into non-empty, mutually disjoint subsets, which means they are the classes of an equivalence relation. Each class has its own unique representative, which is the single element of the class that is also a member of  . The equivalence relation can be expressed formally by
 
and the representatives are the fixed points of  
Applying this to the original example,   and the equivalence classes are:
  •   with representative  
  •   with representative   and
  •   with representative  
Conversely, any partitioning of a set defines an equivalence relation; together with the selection of a representative for each equivalence class, this gives an instance of the situation defined in the question.  --Lambiam 20:47, 19 December 2024 (UTC)Reply
FWIW, the number of such objects on a set of size n is given by OEISA000248, and that page has a number of other combinatorial interpretations. If you ignore the selection of a representative for each class, you get the Bell numbers. --RDBury (talk) 00:35, 21 December 2024 (UTC)Reply

December 20

edit

Give a base b and two base b digits x and z, must there be a base b digits y such that the 3-digit number xyz in base b is prime?

edit

Give a base b and two base b digits x and z (x is not 0, z is coprime to b), must there be a base b digits y such that the 3-digit number xyz in base b is prime? 1.165.207.39 (talk) 02:10, 20 December 2024 (UTC)Reply

In base 5,   is composite for all base-5 Y. GalacticShoe (talk) 03:39, 20 December 2024 (UTC)Reply
  also offers a counterexample. While there are many counterexamples for most odd bases, I did not find any for even bases.  --Lambiam 09:58, 20 December 2024 (UTC)Reply


December 23

edit

Is it possible to make Twisted Edwards curve birationally equivalent to twisted weirestrass curves ?

edit

Is there an equation fo converting a twisted Edwards curve into a tiwsted weierstrass form ? 2A01:E0A:401:A7C0:6D06:298B:1495:F479 (talk) 04:12, 23 December 2024 (UTC)Reply

According to Montgomery curve § Equivalence with twisted Edwards curves, every twisted Edwards curve is birationally equivalent to a Montgomery curve, while Montgomery curve § Equivalence with Weierstrass curves gives a way to transform a Montgomery curve to an elliptic curve in Weierstrass form. I don't see a definition of "twisted Weierstrass", so I don't know if you can give an extra twist in the process. Perhaps this paper, "Efficient Pairing Computation on Twisted Weierstrass Curves" provides the answer; its abstract promises: "In this paper, we construct the twists of twisted Edwards curves in Weierstrass form."  --Lambiam 10:35, 23 December 2024 (UTC)Reply

December 24

edit

How did the Romans do engineering calculations?

edit

The Romans did some impressive engineering. Engineers today use a lot of mathematical calculations when designing stuff. Calculations using Roman numerals strike me as being close to impossible. What did the Romans do? HiLo48 (talk) 05:50, 24 December 2024 (UTC)Reply

The kind of engineering calculations that might have been relevant would mostly have been about statics – specifically the equilibrium of forces acting on a construction, and the ability of the design to withstand these forces, given its dimensions and the mechanical properties of the materials used in the construction, such as density, modulus of elasticity, shear modulus, Young modulus, fracture strength and ultimate tensile strength. In Roman times, only the simplest aspects of all this were understood mathematically, namely the statics of a construction in which all forces work in the same plane, without torque, and the components are perfectly rigid. The notion of assigning a numerical magnitude to these moduli and strengths did not exist, which anyway did not correspond to precisely defined, well-understood concepts. Therefore, engineering was not a science but an art, mainly based on experience in combination with testing on physical models. Any calculations would mostly have been for the amounts and dimensions of construction materials (and the cost thereof), requiring a relatively small number of additions and multiplications.  --Lambiam 19:03, 24 December 2024 (UTC)Reply
Calculating with Roman Numerals might seem impossible, but in some ways it's simpler than our positional system; there are only so many symbols commonly used, and only so many ways to add and multiply them. Once you know all those ways you efficiently can do calculations with them, up to the limits imposed by the system.
And for a lot of things they relied on experience. Romans knew how to build circular arches, but rather than do calculations to build larger arches, or ones with more efficient shapes they used many small circular ones which they knew worked, stacked side by side and sometimes on top of each other. See e.g. any Roman aqueduct or the Colosseum. For materials they probably produce them on site or close by as they're needed.--2A04:4A43:909F:F9FF:FC7B:F1E8:19D6:124C (talk) 20:12, 24 December 2024 (UTC)Reply

Are these sequences mod any natural number n periodic?

edit

The period of Fibonacci number mod n is the Pisano period of n, but are these sequences mod any natural number n also periodic like Fibonacci number mod n?

  1. Lucas number
  2. Pell number
  3. Tribonacci number
  4. Tetranacci number
  5. Newman–Shanks–Williams number
  6. Padovan sequence
  7. Perrin number
  8. Narayana sequence
  9. Motzkin number
  10. Bell number
  11. Fubini number
  12. Euler zigzag number
  13. Partition number OEISA000041
  14. Distinct partition number OEISA000009

42.76.153.22 (talk) 06:06, 24 December 2024 (UTC)Reply

For 1. through 4., see Pisano period#Generalizations. Although 5. through 8. are not explicitly listed, I'm pretty sure the same argument applies for their periodicity as well. GalacticShoe (talk) 07:05, 24 December 2024 (UTC)Reply
For 13, I'm not sure, but I think the partition function is not periodic modulo any nontrivial number, to the point that the few congruences that are satisfied by the function are also very notable, e.g. Ramanujan's congruences. GalacticShoe (talk) 07:23, 24 December 2024 (UTC)Reply
It's possible that a sequences is eventually periodic but not periodic from the start, for example powers of 2 are periodic for any odd n, but for n=2 the sequence is 1, 0, 0, ..., which is only periodic starting with the second entry. In other words a sequence can be become periodic without being pure periodic. A finiteness argument shows that 1-8 are at least eventually periodic, but I don't think it works for the rest. (Pollard's rho algorithm uses this finiteness argument as well.) It says in the article that Bell numbers are periodic mod n for any prime n, but the status for composite n is unclear, at least from the article. Btw, Catalan numbers not on the list?. --RDBury (talk) 08:08, 24 December 2024 (UTC)Reply
PS. 1-8 are pure periodic. In general, if the recurrence can be written in the form F(k) = (some polynomial in F(k-1), F(k-2), ... F(k-d+1) ) ± F(k-d), then F is pure periodic. The reason is that you can solve for F(k-d) and carry out the recursion backwards starting from where the sequence becomes periodic. Since the previous entries are uniquely determined they must follow the same periodic pattern as the rest of the sequence. If the coefficient of F(k-d) is not ±1 then this argument fails and the sequence can be pre-periodic but not pure periodic, at least when n is not relatively prime to the coefficient. --RDBury (talk) 18:12, 24 December 2024 (UTC)Reply
Ah, what was tripping me up was showing pure periodicity, recursing backwards completely slipped my mind. Thanks for the writeup! GalacticShoe (talk) 18:31, 24 December 2024 (UTC)Reply

December 25

edit
  NODES
Idea 1
idea 1
Note 2
Project 1