Placebo

In subject area: Medicine and Dentistry

Placebo can be defined as “any therapeutic procedure without specific activity given to have an effect on a patient but which is without specific activity for the condition being treated” [1].

From: European Journal of Internal Medicine, 2009

Chapters and Articles

You might find these chapters and articles relevant to this topic.

The Placebo Effect

Curtis E Margo MD, MPH, in Survey of Ophthalmology, 1999

The term placebo comes from the Latin “I shall please.” Placebo is a familiar form of therapy used for its nonspecific psychological effect: an inert or innocuous medicine given to satisfy the patient. Placebo interventions are designed to simulate medical therapy but have no specific action against a _target disease.160,162 The nonspecific effect of placebo has come to mean that no biologically plausible explanation exists to account for any causal association between placebo treatment and clinical outcome. A distinction exists between the concept of placebo effect and the traditional definition of placebo as an inert substance, however. The pure placebo has no real pharmacologic action and includes such therapies as sugar pill and saline injection. So-called impure placebos cause some physiologic response, but the response is not relevant to the disease being treated. Most abandoned ineffective drugs and surgeries would fall into the impure placebo category.

Read full article
URL: https://www.sciencedirect.com/science/article/pii/S0039625799000600

Integrating Complementary Medicine Into Cardiovascular Medicine

John H.K. Vogel MD, MACC, ... William L. WintersJr MD, MACC, in Journal of the American College of Cardiology, 2005

Placebo

A placebo is defined as an inert or innocuous treatment that works not because of the therapy itself but because of its suggestive effect. It is considered a mind/body modality, but with some distinct differences. Placebo therapy depends on the power of a patient’s belief that the therapy will be effective (431).

Read full article
URL: https://www.sciencedirect.com/science/article/pii/S073510970501185X

Neurobiology of the Placebo Effect Part II

Panagiotis Zis, Dimos-Dimitrios Mitsikostas, in International Review of Neurobiology, 2018

Abstract

Placebo is an intervention with no therapeutic effect that is used as a control in randomized controlled trials (RCTs). Placebo effects and responses can produce a beneficial effect that cannot be attributed to the properties of the intervention itself, since it is usually inactive, and should, therefore, be due to the patient's expectations about treatment (placebo effects), or confounding factors such as natural history, co-interventions, biases, among other co-factors (placebo responses). However, adverse events (AEs) may occur when using a placebo intervention, a phenomenon that is called nocebo. Like placebo, the nocebo effect is a cognitive and idiosyncratic phenomenon with specific biological bases, controlled by distinctive neurotransmitters within mapped brain areas most likely located within the network of the limbic system.

Nocebo responses has been found to be very prevalent in various neurological conditions, in particular, in many brain disorders including headache, Parkinson's disease, Alzheimer's disease, depression, epilepsy, multiple sclerosis and motor neuron disease. Pooled AE rates in the placebo groups (nocebo AE rates) vary from 25% in the symptomatic treatment for multiple sclerosis RCTs to almost 80% in motor neuron disease RCTs. Pooled dropout rates because of AEs in the placebo groups (i.e., nocebo dropout rates) vary from 2% in multiple sclerosis RCTs to almost 10% in PD RCTs. Across all brain disorders, the nature of AEs reported in the placebo-treated subjects mirrors those reported by active drug-treated subjects, suggesting that awareness of drug side-effect profiles might have influenced patient expectations and, thus, nocebo responses.

Unexplored brain diseases where nocebo should be studied further include mental disorders (i.e., schizophrenia and bipolar disorder), vascular disorders (i.e., acute ischemic stroke, vascular dementia), degenerative disorders (i.e., frontotemporal dementia, Lewy body dementia) and other systemic atrophies of the brain (i.e., hereditary ataxias).

Read full chapter
URL: https://www.sciencedirect.com/science/article/pii/S0074774218300540

Volume 1

Peter W. Bennett ND, in Textbook of Natural Medicine (Fifth Edition), 2020

Origin of the Term Placebo

The original Latin meaning of placebo is “I shall please.”28 Although the term had a purely medical application in the first half of the 20th century, its meaning has been subject to various interpretations throughout the past several hundred years.

Before the 1940s, placebos were pharmacologically inactive substances, such as saline and lactose pills, used to satisfy patients that something was being done for them—in other words, the doctor was “pleasing” the patient. The 1940s and 1950s saw an explosion of the use of double-blind experimental procedures to evaluate the growing number of new drugs and medical procedures. Suspicion arose that all medical therapies contained an element of the placebo phenomenon.29 This new understanding pressed the scientific community to offer new, far broader definitions.

Shapiro25 offered the classic definition of a placebo:

Any therapeutic procedure (or that component of any therapeutic procedure) which is given deliberately to have an effect, or unknowingly has an effect on a patient, symptom, syndrome, or disease, but which is objectively without specific activity for the condition being treated. The therapeutic procedure may be given with or without the conscious knowledge that the procedure is a placebo, may be an active (non-inert) or inactive (inert) procedure, and includes, therefore, all medical procedures no matter how specific—oral and parenteral medications, topical preparations, inhalants, and mechanical, surgical, and psychotherapeutic procedures. The placebo must be differentiated from the placebo effect which may or may not occur and which may be favorable or unfavorable. The placebo effect is defined as the changes produced by placebos. The placebo is also used to describe an adequate control in research.

A more accurate definition would be the following: The placebo effect is the process of a physician working with the self-healing processes of a patient. The placebo response is healing that results from the patient’s own natural survival and homeostatic defense mechanisms.

Modern placebo definitions extend to its nature, properties, and effects. A placebo can be known or unknown, active or inactive, positive or negative in results (placebo effect vs. nocebo effect), and can extend to all forms of diagnostic or therapeutic modalities,30 as further defined in Box 6.1.

Read full chapter
URL: https://www.sciencedirect.com/science/article/pii/B9780323430449000066

Placebo therapy in dermatology

TokeS Barfod MD, in Clinics in Dermatology, 1999

A therapeutic effect after a placebo treatment is more likely when the patient regards the physician as experienced, competent and optimistic,22,23 and when the physician expects the treatment to help.24,25 The physician’s attention may have a positive effect,26 may comfort the patient, and may help by (unconsciously) demonstrating coping techniques in the way the physician responds to the patient’s suffering.

Read full article
URL: https://www.sciencedirect.com/science/article/pii/S0738081X98000613

The Placebo Effect for Gastroenterology: Tool or Torment

Charles N. Bernstein, in Clinical Gastroenterology and Hepatology, 2006

A number of definitions have been presented for placebo. Schapiro6 defined placebo as any therapeutic procedure that has an effect on a patient, symptom, syndrome, or disease, but that objectively is without specific activity for the condition being treated. Brody7 expanded on this definition, defining placebo as a treatment believed not to have a specific effect on the illness or condition to which it is applied, and the placebo effect as the aspect of treatment not attributable to specific pharmacologic or physiologic properties. Furthermore, the placebo effect was considered to be the symbolic significance of a treatment changing a patient’s illness.7 A more positive spin on placebo is the definition of the placebo effect as “remembered wellness.”2

Read full article
URL: https://www.sciencedirect.com/science/article/pii/S1542356506008949

Integrating Complementary Medicine Into Cardiovascular Medicine

John H.K. Vogel MD, MACC, ... William L. WintersJr MD, MACC, in Journal of the American College of Cardiology, 2005

Placebo

Placebo,” Latin for “I shall please,” can be derived from a device, a drug, or complementary medicine modalities. A placebo is not necessarily a sham therapy but a potential response due to an interaction between the intent of the healer and the expectations of the patient. The response can be powerful, but the longevity of the response can vary by condition and type of placebo. Several reports in cardiology—BHAT (278), CHF-STAT trial (279), and the Coronary Drug Project (280)—have shown a remarkably strong effect regarding compliance with placebo. The reduction in mortality for those who take their placebo compared to those who are non-compliant is highly significant, but the mechanism (280) is unknown.

Shapiro (281) indicated that the physician was important in the dyadic dance of healing and proposed that perhaps doctors, independent of what they did, were actually potent placebos in their own right. He and others enumerated a number of specific variables that might endow some physicians with particular curative manna: enthusiasm for treatment, apparent warm feelings for the patient, confidence, and authority. Some physicians may be able to exhibit a placebo effect more intensely than others, but the mechanism for this and the extent of it are not understood.

The placebo effect has been described as a nonspecific psychological or psychophysiologic therapeutic effect, but this may not be correct and the response may be a crucial synergistic adjunct to any cardiovascular therapy. Placebos can elicit a real and substantial response, the extent of which is related to the type of the placebo, the condition being treated, and the response being elicited. No multivariate analysis has detected which specific patient characteristics are most associated with a profound placebo effect. The placebo response in major depression (282) ranges from 32% to 70% and can equal that of a drug intervention. After all, what occurs during psychotherapy is a form of placebo response. The importance of understanding the mechanisms responsible for the placebo response is crucial to understanding the basic nature of healing (283). Expectancy, beliefs, anxiety, hope, trust, and intent can alter outcomes regarding disease (284).

The placebo response may involve disease expression, specific neuroendocrine, neuronal and immune intermediary pathways, neuropeptides, enkephalins, endorphins, cholecystokinin, neurohormones (including glucocorticoids and prolactin), neurotransmitters (including 5-hydroxytryptamine, norepinephrine, dopamine), and other messengers such as nitric acid and prostaglandins. The power of expectancy of improvement was emphasized by controlled trials of arthroscopic surgery and of neurosurgery. Osteoarthritis of the knee responds as well to arthroscopic debridement, arthroscopic lavage, and placebo surgery. Similarly, sham neurosurgery improved Parkinson patients as well as cell implants and sham cardiovascular surgery improves patient chest pain as often as 90% of the time (285). It is, however, difficult to quantitate the benefit of either the placebo effect or sham procedure.

Hrobjartsson and Gotzsche (286) suggest there is little evidence that placebos in specific conditions, comparing no therapy to placebo therapy, had powerful clinical effects. Yet this is likely disease specific as many placebo-controlled studies showed enormous benefits of the placebo (282). Another form of the placebo response is relief to a patient when serious disease is excluded. Patients who have an evaluation (“tests”) for atypical chest pain are less likely to be disabled than those who do not have such an evaluation (287).

Read full article
URL: https://www.sciencedirect.com/science/article/pii/S073510970501185X

Nonpharmaceutical options for pediatric headache: Nutraceuticals, manual therapies, and acupuncture☆

Amanda Hall MSN, FNP-C, ... Sita Kedia MD, MPH, in Pediatric Headache, 2022

Placebo

Placebo, a complex response involving neurobiological and neuropsychological mechanisms,177 is thought to be higher amongst pediatric patients with headaches.8 Prescribing placebo is a long standing ethical controversy largely due to the misconception that patients need to be deceived for the treatment to work. Some studies suggest placebo may still be elicited in both pediatric patients and patients with migraine when the placebo mechanism is disclosed, negating the need for deception.178,179 Since prophylactic medications carry the risk of adverse effects and do not outcompete placebo in pediatric headache,5 acupuncture may be seen as a more benign placebo prescription for some individuals.

Eliciting placebo via “true” or “sham” points via needles, electrical stimulation, laser stimulation, or acupressure may be most effective when patients report benefits from acupuncture in the past or enthusiastically express interest in the modality. If prescribing acupuncture, consider also presenting placebo as a validated approach comprised of complicated neurobiological and neuropsychological effects, with efficacy comparable to medications and fewer adverse effects reported. Behavioral therapies, manual therapies, devices, and nutraceuticals could be considered first when reviewing nonmedication treatments since they are arguably less invasive.

Read full chapter
URL: https://www.sciencedirect.com/science/article/pii/B9780323830058000252

Stem Cell Therapies for Neurodegenerative Disorders: An Ethical Analysis

Sorin Hostiuc, ... Mihaela Hostiuc, in Clinical Ethics At the Crossroads of Genetic and Reproductive Technologies, 2018

3 Use of Placebo Controls in Sham Surgery1

Placebo is a form of simulated medical treatment intended to deceive the patient/subject who believes that he/she received an active, beneficial, medical intervention. In clinical medicine, the use of placebo is allowed in particular circumstances, and for particular pathologies, such as depression, anxiety, or surgical-related pain. The use of placebo is limited in clinical medicine because it can generate distrust within the physician-patient relationship. Siegler argued that placebo could be used in clinical practice if four conditions are simultaneously met: (1) the condition is known to respond well to placebo, (2) the alternative to placebo is either continued illness or the use of a drug with known adverse risks or addiction, (3) the patient wishes to be treated, and (4) the patient insists on obtaining a prescription from the physician (2010).

In medical research, placebo is more often used, in the control arm, if there is not a best-alternative-treatment (BAT) to which the active intervention could be compared. Investigators use placebo to differentiate the real effect, caused by an active intervention, from subjective effects, caused by the belief of the subject that he/she has received a beneficial medical intervention. A major advantage of placebo-controlled trials compared to BAT-controlled trials is the difference in effect sizes between the cases and control groups. Compared to BAT, in placebo-controlled trials the effect-size is higher, and the number of subjects needed to reach a certain statistical power is lower. Other reasons in favor of placebo-controlled trials include: (1) a new therapy might not be better concerning the primary outcome compared with the best available therapy, but it might be advantageous in other ways (safety, compliance, tolerability, cost), (2) the best available therapy control might show an inconsistency in effects caused by methodological differences (e.g., the inclusion criteria, that might be different compared to the ones used to prove its usefulness), and (3) the presence of methodological limitations in using the best available therapy option (Castro, 2007). For these reasons, researchers tend to prefer placebo instead of best alternative randomized controlled trials, and often try to “bend the rules” and develop research protocols using placebo when an alternate plan could be designed.

The use of placebo in surgery trials is even more controversial. Clark, for example, considered that, unlike placebo-controlled trials in pharmacological research, sham surgeries “fail the test of beneficence” (Clark, 2002). Weijer gave some persuasive arguments for this, including the absence of a therapeutic purpose, important scientific disadvantages, and a noteworthy risk increase (2002). Some authors developed specific ethical frameworks for the use of sham procedures in trials. For example, Horns and Miller provided a six-step ethical framework for assessing the acceptability of sham surgeries, which included: “1) there is a valuable, clinically relevant question to be answered by the research, 2) the placebo control is methodologically necessary to test the study hypothesis, 3) the risk of the placebo control itself has been minimized, 4) the risk of a placebo control does not exceed a threshold of acceptable research risk, 5) the risk of the placebo control is justified by valuable knowledge to be gained, and 6) the misleading involved in the administration of a placebo control is adequately disclosed and authorized during the informed consent process” (2003).

3.1 Is Sham Surgery Accepted by Potential Subjects?

Even though the potential subjects’ acceptability of a clinical trial is not a de facto mandatory condition for its initiation, a low acceptability score could render the process of finding/selecting subjects cumbersome. Therefore, one of the first questions that should be asked by any investigator who aims to perform sham surgery should be related to the subjects’ acceptability of the procedure. There have been a few studies dealing specifically with this issue. Frank et al. performed a study on subjects with and without PD to assess their willingness to participate in neurosurgical trials for this disease. The investigators selected three groups of patients: with PD, without PD but with other neurological diseases (dementia excluded), and patients from primary care. They then gave each the option to be either included in an unblinded trial, a blinded trial, or not to participate at all. Most subjects from each group preferred to be included in the unblinded trial. The highest number of subjects selecting nonparticipation was in the PD group (34%, while in the other two the maximum nonparticipation portion accounted for 10.4%). Also, the PD group of subjects was the least willing one to be involved in a blinded study (24.5%, while the other groups favored this option in a percent from 35% to 40%) (Frank et al., 2008). The authors concluded: “patients with PD, when compared with patients with non-PD neurology or primary care, may have adapted to their chronic illness and may not be so desperate that they would be more eager to participate in risky research. In fact, they appear more cautious” (Frank et al., 2008). The conclusion is subjective, and not based on the actual study. Maybe, for example, the PD patients did not want to be included in the blinded trial because they were directly affected by the procedure, and felt the risks were too high. Whenever we would like to analyze the opinions of patients regarding a certain medical procedure, we must take into account all the possible reasons for a certain response, and whether their replies are in line with their actual beliefs. Such patient surveys tend to be performed more frequently and used as objective proofs, suggesting that patients agree with more controversial issues, not taking into account the validity of the questionnaires that are used or the mere fact that, for a certain procedure to be agreed upon, needs to be obtained an individual consent and not a population agreement regarding its usefulness. Moore et al., in the TransEuro project, found that subjects enrolled in PD clinical trials tend to be more educated, younger, with a higher cognitive score, and better motor function compared to patients who were eligible, but not included in the trial, and argued that this could raise problems regarding a parity of access to clinical trials (Moore et al., 2014). However, this could also be a method of protecting vulnerable subjects. Swift, in a qualitative study about the perspective of the patients and their relatives about sham surgery in PD, showed that participation was acceptable for a small majority of interviewers, but the main reasons for accepting it seemed to be the severity of the disease and the lack of good treatment options. Moreover, the surveyed persons preferred real to sham surgery; this comes to support the idea that subjects see themselves primarily as patients, that the acceptance for participating in clinical trials is not based on altruistic reasons (Swift, 2012), and that therapeutic misconception might be significant.

3.2 Sham Surgery as a Form of Mitigated Trolley

Albin believes that sham surgery could be seen as a form of mitigated trolley (2005). The trolley dilemma is often used to test the moral intuition for circumstances in which a few people are put at risk to save more. In this problem, a runaway trolley goes down a track toward five men who will be killed if it is not stopped or diverted. The trolley cannot be stopped, but it can be diverted. However, on the secondary line, there is another person who will be killed by the trolley. Therefore should one save five with the price of one life through action, or save one and have the other five die by not acting? Albin considers that sham surgery can be partially assimilated with a trolley in which the conductor diverts the line but puts a padding on the front, to cushion the impact of the trolley. The decision similar to the one made by the trolley conductor is to perform a clinical trial, and subsequently to put some people at a mitigated risk (the surgery is partially simulated, so cushioned), to aid many (Albin, 2005). What is wrong with this approach? Even if it apparently leads to a maximization of the benefits, and is often used by the supporters of utilitarian ethics in health care, we believe that it contradicts the utilitarian moral theory. Jeremy Bentham, in his book Deontology of the Science of Morality, said that an action is correct or incorrect, deserving or not, receiving approval or disapproval, reported to the tendency in which it causes the increase or decrease in the quantity of public happiness (Bentham, 1834). This means that, when we analyze whether an act is moral or immoral from a utilitarian perspective, we should examine not only the good done to the ones directly affected by our actions but also the good generated by them in the general population. If a physician saves a few lives at the expense of sacrificing one, apparently, he does more good directly; however, his actions might cause a decrease in the trust in physicians in general—Why should I, as a patient, go to a doctor if he might sacrifice me for the good of others? This decrease in trust would cause a decreased addressability of patients toward the health-care system, and a decreased therapeutic compliance, therefore causing more harm overall. Similarly, this could decrease the trust in clinical trials, and subsequently the number of potential subjects willing to participate.

3.3 Risk to Benefit Analysis

One of the major reasons for accepting sham surgeries is represented by the fact that minor risks for a few patients are considered to be less important than the overall potential benefit the results of the study might lead to, for both the subject and the population potentially benefiting from it. For example, Olanow et al. stated, as a conclusion of their study, that “This study did not confirm the clinical benefits reported in open-label trials. Furthermore, unanticipated and potentially disabling off-medication dyskinesias developed in greater than 50% of patients. We cannot therefore recommend fetal nigral transplantation as a therapy for PD at this time. It is possible, however, that enhanced benefits can be obtained in patients with milder disease, with transplantation of higher numbers of cells, and with more prolonged immunosuppression” (Olanow et al., 2003). Therefore even if more than 50% of all subjects developed “unanticipated and potentially disabling off-medication dyskinesias,” the authors concluded that more studies should be performed to search for additional potentially beneficial effects, and not to specifically search for methods of minimizing the risks for subjects, and possibly, patients.

The potential benefit for patients with PD is significant if the therapy will actually have a positive clinical effect. Another question we must ask is how would the subjects from the control group benefit from it? Normally, if a medical intervention is shown to be beneficial during a clinical trial, the subjects from the placebo group would receive the same procedure after the end of the trial; therefore, they would benefit from all the positive results of the trial without risking any unforeseen complication generated by the implantation of fetal stem cells in their brains. However, for this purpose, they would suffer two surgical interventions (one for the trial and one for the therapy), which might be associated with significant risks, especially taking into account the fact that most patients are old, with a severe pathology, and subsequently have a higher surgical risk. Performing sham surgery on patients with PD, puts them at a more than minimal risk, especially regarding anesthesia-related, which should warrant a careful analysis of the benefit differential compared to less invasive measures. Weijer considered that sham surgical procedures should be analyzed as nontherapeutic interventions, and argued that a nonsurgery control is likely a better option. According to him, therapeutic procedures should pass a test of clinical equipoise, and a harm-to-benefit analysis should be performed. Nontherapeutic procedures do not offer the prospect of benefits to the individual subject, and therefore, the harm-to-benefit analysis is not appropriate. Instead, this analysis should be replaced with the minimization of the risks consistent with a sound design and the reasonability of the risks in relation to the knowledge to be gained (Weijer, 2002). By using these principles regarding risk analysis, the use of sham surgery should be forbidden. Minimization of risks, in nontherapeutic interventions, cannot be correlated with the magnitude of the benefit; therefore, any risks that are more than minimal are in contradiction with the principle of nonmaleficence, and should not be allowed in clinical trials using sham controls.

3.4 What Role Should Collateral Benefits Have in the Decision to Allow Sham Surgery?

Beside a direct benefit for the subjects, derived from the actual therapeutic intervention, the possibility for clinical trial subjects to receive collateral benefits generated by the inclusion in the trials is sometimes discussed. In this case, all subjects would benefit from the best possible treatment (Emanuel and Emanuel, 1992; Hostiuc, 2014a,b; King, 2000). Nancy King argued that collateral benefits should not be used as types of benefits included in the risk analysis of clinical trials for two main reasons: (1) by providing a potentially higher standard of care for subjects compared to patients, we might potentially discourage the improvement of the standard treatment, and (2) as collateral benefits are under the control of the investigators/sponsors, they might become a means of manipulating or even coercing vulnerable patients to enter the clinical trial (King, 2000). We agree with her opinion, that these collateral benefits should not be taken into account as an element of the risk to benefit analysis. However, if the study generates such a benefit, the participants should receive it, as a reward for their altruistic participation in the study.

3.5 Are Placebo-Controlled Trials Actually Needed in Surgery Studies?

We presented above a few reasons for which investigators prefer placebo to BAT in randomized clinical trials. These reasons (and others) might cause them to try a slight bend of the strict ethical rules governing the use of placebo in clinical trials. For example, Dekkers and Boer argued that, for Parkinson's trials, an alternate design could consist of a core assessment procedure, in which measurement protocols are applied to the subjects before and after the surgical intervention (2001). Avins argues that unbalanced randomization might be less morally problematic in some instances, with the risk, however, of losing statistical power (1998). Macklin suggested that “Cellular-based surgical therapies have much in common with pharmacologic treatments and lend themselves to evaluation in randomized, double-blind, placebo-controlled trial” (1999). Even if this approach is viable from a scientific point of view, this is not necessarily the case from a moral viewpoint. The risks associated with anesthesia and a surgical procedure are inherently higher than in most pharmacological clinical trials, especially for older individuals with severe associated pathologies. If they are to be accepted by the potential subjects, this is because of an inherent wish to get better and to receive an experimental treatment with significant benefits from a health-care point of view (Swift, 2012; Weijer, 2002). Between these two types of therapies are also substantial differences regarding the way concepts like autonomy, therapeutic misconception, and trust are perceived by the patients. Therefore we should not try to minimize, but rather emphasize, the differences between surgical and clinical trials in order to reveal the particularities of the latter. Only by doing this the ethical issues raised in practice by sham surgery are maximized and the therapeutic misconception can be minimized.

3.6 Autonomy Versus Therapeutic Misconception

According to Lidz and Applebaum, therapeutic misconception occurs “when a research subject fails to appreciate the distinction between the imperatives of clinical research and of ordinary treatment, and therefore inaccurately attributes therapeutic intent to research procedure” (Lidz and Appelbaum, 2002). The therapeutic misconception may be caused by the patient's expectations that the investigation will act in his/hers best interest even during a clinical trial, by the lack of understanding regarding the concept of randomization, by treatment constraints associated with clinical trials, or by a wish that the study will be beneficent to them (Byrne and Thompson, 2006). There are two main responses to therapeutic misconception: to accept it as an inevitable consequence of clinical trials or to implement measures whose purpose is to reduce it, including the use of the “neutral discloser,” rewriting the informed consent forms, changes in the information algorithm used by physicians when trying to enroll a patient in a clinical trial, changes in monetary rewards, and research advertisements (Emanuel, 2008, pp. 633–644). Therapeutic misconception is especially high in fields in which the patients are highly vulnerable like oncology or psychiatry (Hostiuc, 2015). We believe that surgery could also fit in this category as a patient scheduled for a surgical procedure most likely expects a direct benefit resulting from the intervention. Moreover, sometimes even the proper information might not change his/her preconception regarding the clinical utility of the surgery. Therefore, to minimize therapeutic misconception, subjects must be explicitly informed about the sham surgery and the understanding by the subjects of this issue should be tested explicitly before they sign the informed consent.

The above-presented list is by no means exhaustive; it shows, however, the complexity of the problem and the difficulties of its ethical analysis. A series of guidelines have been developed regarding the possibility of using placebo (sham surgeries) in research, of which one of the easiest and most useful for surgical investigators is the one by Tenery et al., who based their ethical analysis on the following elements: (1) Placebo-controlled trials should only be used in surgery if there are no other designs that could lead to the necessary information. (2) Special care should be given to the obtaining of the informed consent. The potential subjects should clearly know the risk and the particularities of each arm of the study, with an emphasis on the interventions that would/would not be performed. It is recommended for a third party (not the investigator) to obtain the informed consent. (3) Placebo controls should not be used when the investigators investigate the usefulness of a slightly modified surgical procedure. (4) Placebo controls should be allowed when a surgical procedure is developed for an affliction for which there is no surgical treatment, or if the efficiency of the standard surgical procedure is questionable, and if it is known that the affliction is potentially influenced by placebo, or if the risks of the placebo intervention are small. (5) If the surgical treatment has high risks, and the standard, nonmedical treatment is efficient and acceptable to the patients, it should be offered in all the arms of the study (2002). Additionally, we believe that a first step should consist of a proper analysis of the acceptability of the sham surgery by potential subjects. Moreover, specific measures should be taken to minimize issues like coercion generated by potential collateral benefits, or therapeutic misconception.

Read full chapter
URL: https://www.sciencedirect.com/science/article/pii/B9780128137642000106